Conscious vision for action versus unconscious vision for action?
- PMID: 21790744
- DOI: 10.1111/j.1551-6709.2011.01171.x
Conscious vision for action versus unconscious vision for action?
Abstract
David Milner and Melvyn Goodale's dissociation hypothesis is commonly taken to state that there are two functionally specialized cortical streams of visual processing originating in striate (V1) cortex: a dorsal, action-related "unconscious" stream and a ventral, perception-related "conscious" stream. As Milner and Goodale acknowledge, findings from blindsight studies suggest a more sophisticated picture that replaces the distinction between unconscious vision for action and conscious vision for perception with a tripartite division between unconscious vision for action, conscious vision for perception, and unconscious vision for perception. The combination excluded by the tripartite division is the possibility of conscious vision for action. But are there good grounds for concluding that there is no conscious vision for action? There is now overwhelming evidence that illusions and perceived size can have a significant effect on action (Bruno & Franz, 2009; Dassonville & Bala, 2004; Franz & Gegenfurtner, 2008; McIntosh & Lashley, 2008). There is also suggestive evidence that any sophisticated visual behavior requires collaboration between the two visual streams at every stage of the process (Schenk & McIntosh, 2010). I nonetheless want to make a case for the tripartite division between unconscious vision for action, conscious vision for perception, and unconscious vision for perception. My aim here is not to refute the evidence showing that conscious vision can affect action but rather to argue (a) that we cannot gain cognitive access to action-guiding dorsal stream representations, and (b) that these representations do not correlate with phenomenal consciousness. This vindicates the semi-conservative view that the dissociation hypothesis is best understood as a tripartite division.
Copyright © 2011 Cognitive Science Society, Inc.
Similar articles
-
Are there unconscious perceptual processes?Conscious Cogn. 2011 Jun;20(2):449-63. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2010.10.002. Epub 2010 Dec 10. Conscious Cogn. 2011. PMID: 21146426 Review.
-
Grasping visual illusions: consistent data and no dissociation.Cogn Neuropsychol. 2008 Oct-Dec;25(7-8):920-50. Cogn Neuropsychol. 2008. PMID: 19378412
-
Action without perception in human vision.Cogn Neuropsychol. 2008 Oct-Dec;25(7-8):891-919. doi: 10.1080/02643290801961984. Cogn Neuropsychol. 2008. PMID: 18608333 Review.
-
An evolving view of duplex vision: separate but interacting cortical pathways for perception and action.Curr Opin Neurobiol. 2004 Apr;14(2):203-11. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2004.03.002. Curr Opin Neurobiol. 2004. PMID: 15082326 Review.
-
Conscious Vision in Action.Cogn Sci. 2015 Sep;39(7):1435-67. doi: 10.1111/cogs.12226. Epub 2015 Apr 2. Cogn Sci. 2015. PMID: 25845648 Review.
Cited by
-
Subliminal (latent) processing of pain and its evolution to conscious awareness.Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2018 May;88:1-15. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2018.02.015. Epub 2018 Feb 21. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2018. PMID: 29476771 Free PMC article. Review.
-
Unconscious Imagination and the Mental Imagery Debate.Front Psychol. 2017 May 23;8:799. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00799. eCollection 2017. Front Psychol. 2017. PMID: 28588527 Free PMC article. Review.
-
Conscious Action/Zombie Action.Nous. 2016 Jun;50(2):419-444. doi: 10.1111/nous.12086. Epub 2015 Jan 9. Nous. 2016. PMID: 27667859 Free PMC article.
-
Conscious Control over Action.Mind Lang. 2015 Jun;30(3):320-344. doi: 10.1111/mila.12082. Mind Lang. 2015. PMID: 26113753 Free PMC article.
-
Decoupled visually-guided reaching in optic ataxia: differences in motor control between canonical and non-canonical orientations in space.PLoS One. 2013 Dec 31;8(12):e86138. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0086138. eCollection 2013. PLoS One. 2013. PMID: 24392035 Free PMC article.
MeSH terms
LinkOut - more resources
Full Text Sources
Research Materials