Skip to main page content
U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

Dot gov

The .gov means it’s official.
Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

Https

The site is secure.
The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

Access keys NCBI Homepage MyNCBI Homepage Main Content Main Navigation
Review
. 2022 Oct 3:13:750313.
doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.750313. eCollection 2022.

Compassionate Conservation is indistinguishable from traditional forms of conservation in practice

Affiliations
Review

Compassionate Conservation is indistinguishable from traditional forms of conservation in practice

Christopher A Bobier et al. Front Psychol. .

Abstract

Animal welfare and ethics are important factors influencing wildlife conservation practice, and critics are increasingly challenging the underlying ethics and motivations supporting common conservation practices. "Compassionate Conservationists" argue that all conservationists should respect the rights of individual sentient animals and approach conservation problems from a position of compassion, and that doing so requires implementing practices that avoid direct harm to individual animals. In this way Compassionate Conservationists seek to contrast themselves with "Traditional Conservationists" who often express consequentialist decision-making processes that ostensibly aim to dispassionately minimize net animal harms, resulting in the common use of practices that directly harm or kill some animals. Conservationists and other observers might therefore conclude that the two sides of this debate are distinct and/or that their policy proscriptions produce different welfare outcomes for animals. To explore the validity of this conclusion we review the ethical philosophies underpinning two types of Compassionate Conservation-deontology and virtue ethics. Deontology focusses on animal rights or the moral duties or obligations of conservationists, whereas virtue ethics focusses on acting in ways that are virtuous or compassionate. We demonstrate that both types permit the intentional harm and killing of animals when faced with common conservation problems where animals will be harmed no matter what the conservationist does or does not do. We then describe the applied decision-making processes exhibited by Compassionate Conservationists (of both types) and Traditional Conservationists to show that they may each lead to the implementation of similar conservation practices (including lethal control) and produce similar outcomes for animals, despite the perceived differences in their ethical motivations. The widespread presence of wildlife conservation problems that cannot be resolved without causing at least some harm to some animals means that conservationists of all persuasions must routinely make trade-offs between the welfare of some animals over others. Compassionate Conservationists do this from an explicit position of animal rights and/or compassion, whereas Traditional Conservationists respect animal rights and exhibit this same compassion implicitly. These observations lead to the conclusion that Compassionate Conservation is indistinguishable from traditional forms of conservation in practice, and that the apparent disagreement among conservationists primarily concerns the effectiveness of various wildlife management practices at minimizing animal harm, and not the underlying ethics, motivations or morality of those practices.

Keywords: animal welfare; decision-making; invasive species; lethal control; virtue ethics; wildlife management.

PubMed Disclaimer

Conflict of interest statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

    1. Abbate C. (2014). Virtues and animals: a minimally decent ethic for practical living in a non-ideal world. J. Agric. Environ. Ethics 27, 909–929. doi: 10.1007/s10806-014-9505-z - DOI
    1. Abbate C. (2020). Animal rights and the duty to harm: when to be a harm causing deontologist. Zeitschrift Für Ethik Und Moralphilosophie 3, 5–26. doi: 10.1007/s42048-020-00059-3 - DOI
    1. Akrivou K., Scalzo G., Orón J. V. (2020). “The moral psychology of practical wisdom for business and management,” in Handbook of Practical Wisdom in Business and Management. eds. Schwartz B., Bernacchio C., González-Cantón C., Robson A. (Berlin: Springer; ), 1–16.
    1. Akrivou K., Scalzo G., Semper J. V. O. (2019). The Inter-processual Self: Towards a Personalist Virtue Ethics Proposal for Human Agency. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
    1. Allen B. L., Allen L. R., Ballard G., Drouilly M., Fleming P. J. S., Hampton J. O., et al. . (2019). Animal welfare considerations for using large carnivores and guardian dogs as vertebrate biocontrol tools against other animals. Biol. Conserv. 232, 258–270. doi: 10.1016/j.biocon.2019.02.019 - DOI

LinkOut - more resources